Day 14 -- The Abandonment of the Christian/Enlightenment Idea of a Common Humanity Tzvetan Todorov, On Human Diversity: Nationalism, Racism, and Exoticism in French Thought (Cambridge. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1993, pp.106-107. [p.106] I shall focus here on Renan and Le Bon, for
their representativeness: the former because he was one of the most
influential thinkers of the nineteenth century, the latter because he was a
talented popularizer whose works, translated into some ten languages sold
hundreds of thousands of copies (this is the case in particular with
The Psychology of Peoples). Renan
and Le Bon also have their own more original ideas on the subject of race,
but I shall set these aside for a time so as to concentrate on the
sedimentations, in their work, of the ordinary anonymous racialist ideology
of the period, a sort of racial common sense that could have appeared in a
"Dictionary of received ideas" of the time. The original aspect of Renan's contribution, as we
shall see, involves the opposition between the Aryan and Semitic, "races."
What is not original, what he does not ponder at length, what he is content
merely to transmit, is the division of humanity into several major race –
white, yellow, and black -- and the hierarchization of this division. The
three races have separate origins . . . Philology, he believed, had managed
to establish the common origin of all whites . . . but the [p.107] other
varieties of the human species are not included: philology “recoils at doing
the same for the Chinese race, even more so for the inferior races” – that
is, black (Histoire générale et
système compare des langues sémitiques [General History and Comparative
System of the Semitic Languages], p. 587). Like Renan, Gobineau, and Taine whose work he most often simply summarizes and systematizes, Le Bon is a partisan of polygenesis [the theory that different groups of human came into being entirely separately from one another], and he equates the human races with animal species (something Buffon rightly refused to do). “By the aid of clearly defined anatomical characteristics, such as the colour of the skin, and the shape and volume of the skull, it has been possible to establish that the human race comprises several species which are quite distinct and probably of very different origin” (The Psychology of People, p.4) If the term “race” is used in preference to “species,” Le Bon suggests, it is in order to avoid offending Christian sensitivities, for Christians maintain that all men belong to the same species: here science is opposed to religious prejudice. . . . For Renan, the inferior race includes black
Africans, Australian aborigines, and American Indians (these groups link by
virtue of their cultural inferiority rather on the basis of common physical
features). Renan assumes that in
the beginning the whole earth was overrun with members of these races; they
have been progressively eliminated by members of other races. “Whenever the
Aryans and the Semites went – in fact, in every country where they settled –
they encountered half-savage races that they exterminated” (Histoire
general, p., 585). Let us
note that no value judgments accompanies the report of exterminations.
The inferior races are defined not only by their primitive or
civilized status but by their inability to become civilized, their lack of
susceptibility to progress” (p.586). “Furthermore, we do not have a single
example of a savage population that has moved up to civilization” (581).
Elsewhere, Renan speaks of: ”the everlasting infancy of those
non-perfectible races” (The Future of
Science, p.152_, of “peoples doomed to remain stationary” (p.155)
The break with the humanist ideal is quite clear: what Rousseau [1712-1778]
had presented as a distinctive feature of the human species – that is, its
perfectibility – is denied to part of humanity.
. . .
|